Not logged in | Create account | Login

    Authorpædia Trademarks

    Social buttons

    Languages

    Read

    AUTHORPÆDIA is hosted by Authorpædia Foundation, Inc. a U.S. non-profit organization.

W. Andrew Robinson

The postulate that consciousness causes collapse is an interpretation of quantum mechanics in which consciousness is postulated to be the main mechanism behind the process of measurement in quantum mechanics. It is a historical interpretation of quantum mechanics but that is largely discarded by modern physicists. The idea is attributed to Eugene Wigner who wrote about it in the 1960s, but traces of the idea appear as early as the 1930s. Wigner later rejected this interpretation in the 1970s and 1980s.

History

Earlier work

In his 1932 book Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, John von Neumann argued that the mathematics of quantum mechanics allows the collapse of the wave function to be placed at any position in the causal chain from the measurement device to the "subjective perception" of the human observer.[1] However von Neumann did not explicitly relate measurement with consciousness.[1][2] In 1939, Fritz London and Edmond Bauer argued that the consciousness of the observer played an important role in measurement.[3][1] However London wrote about consciousness in terms of philosophical phenomenology and not necessarily as a physical process.[2]

Wigner' work

The idea of "consciousness causes collapse" is attributed to Eugene Wigner who first wrote about it in his 1961 article "Remarks on the mind-body question" and developed it further during the 1960s.[1] Wigner reformulated the Schrödinger's cat thought experiment as the Wigner's friend and proposed that the consciousness of an observer is the demarcation line that precipitates collapse of the wave function, independent of any realist interpretation.[4][2] The mind is postulated to be non-physical and the only true measurement apparatus.[5][2]

The idea was criticized early by Abner Shimony in 1963 and by Hilary Putnam a year later.[2]

Wigner discarded the conscious collapse interpretation in the later 1970s. In a lecture 1982, Wigner says that he early view of quantum mechanics should be criticized as solipsism. In 1984, he writes that he was convinced out of it by the 1970 work of H. Dieter Zeh on quantum decoherence and macroscopic quantum phenomena.[6]

After Wigner

The idea of consciousness causing collapse has been promoted and developed by Henry Stapp since 1993.[1]

Description

Measurement in standard quantum mechanics

In the orthodox Copenhagen interpretation, quantum mechanics predicts only the probabilities for different observed experimental outcomes. What constitutes an observer or an measurement is not directly specified by the theory, and the behavior of a system under measurement and observation is completely different from its usual behavior: the wavefunction that describes a system spreads out into an ever-larger superposition of different possible situations. However, during observation, the wavefunction describing the system collapses to one of several options. If there is no observation, this collapse does not occur, and none of the options ever become less likely.[7]

It can be predicted using quantum mechanics, absent a collapse postulate, that an observer observing a quantum superposition will turn into a superposition of different observers seeing different things. The observer will have a wavefunction which describes all the possible outcomes. Still, in actual experience, an observer never senses a superposition, but always senses that one of the outcomes has occurred with certainty. This apparent conflict between a wavefunction description and classical experience is called the problem of observation (see Measurement problem).[8]

Consciousness-causes-collapse interpretation

This consciousness causes collapse interpretation has been summarized thus:[5]

The rules of quantum mechanics are correct but there is only one system which may be treated with quantum mechanics, namely the entire material world. There exist external observers which cannot be treated within quantum mechanics, namely human (and perhaps animal) minds, which perform measurements on the brain causing wave function collapse.

Stapp has argued for the concept as follows:[9]

From the point of view of the mathematics of quantum theory it makes no sense to treat a measuring device as intrinsically different from the collection of atomic constituents that make it up. A device is just another part of the physical universe... Moreover, the conscious thoughts of a human observer ought to be causally connected most directly and immediately to what is happening in his brain, not to what is happening out at some measuring device... Our bodies and brains thus become ... parts of the quantum mechanically described physical universe. Treating the entire physical universe in this unified way provides a conceptually simple and logically coherent theoretical foundation...

Objections to the interpretation

Wigner shifted away from "consciousness causes collapse" in his later years. This was partly because he was embarrassed that "consciousness causes collapse" can lead to a kind of solipsism, but also because he decided that he had been wrong to try to apply quantum physics at the scale of everyday life (specifically, he rejected his initial idea of treating macroscopic objects as isolated systems).[6]

This interpretation relies upon an interactionist form of dualism that is inconsistent with the materialism that is commonly used to understand the brain, and accepted by most scientists.[5] (Materialism assumes that consciousness has no special role in relation to quantum mechanics.)[5] The measurement problem notwithstanding, they point to a causal closure of physics, suggesting a problem with how consciousness and matter might interact, reminiscent of objections to Descartes' substance dualism.

The only form of interactionist dualism that has seemed even remotely tenable in the contemporary picture is one that exploits certain properties of quantum mechanics. There are two ways this might go. First, some [e.g., Eccles 1986] have appealed to the existence of quantum indeterminacy, and have suggested that a nonphysical consciousness might be responsible for filling the resultant causal gaps, determining which values some physical magnitudes might take within an apparently "probabilistic" distribution... This is an audacious and interesting suggestion, but it has a number of problems... A second way in which quantum mechanics bears on the issue of causal closure lies with the fact that in some interpretations of the quantum formalism, consciousness itself plays a vital causal role, being required to bring about the so-called "collapse of the wave-function." This collapse is supposed to occur upon any act of measurement; and in one interpretation, the only way to distinguish a measurement from a nonmeasurement is via the presence of consciousness. This theory is certainly not universally accepted (for a start, it presupposes that consciousness is not itself physical, surely contrary to the views of most physicists), and I do not accept it myself, but in any case it seems that the kind of causal work consciousness performs here is quite different from the kind required for consciousness to play a role in directing behavior... In any case, all versions of interactionist dualism have a conceptual problem that suggests that they are less successful in avoiding epiphenomenalism than they might seem; or at least they are no better off than naturalistic dualism. Even on these views, there is a sense in which the phenomenal is irrelevant. We can always subtract the phenomenal component from any explanatory account, yielding a purely causal component.[10]

— David Chalmers, "The Irreducibility of Consciousness" in The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory

The interpretation has also been criticized for not explaining which things have sufficient consciousness to collapse the wave function. Also, it posits an important role for the conscious mind, and it has been questioned how this could be the case for the earlier universe, before consciousness had evolved or emerged. It has been argued that "[consciousness causes collapse] does not allow sensible discussion of Big Bang cosmology or biological evolution".[5] For example, Roger Penrose remarked: "[T]he evolution of conscious life on this planet is due to appropriate mutations having taken place at various times. These, presumably, are quantum events, so they would exist only in linearly superposed form until they finally led to the evolution of a conscious being—whose very existence depends on all the right mutations having 'actually' taken place!"[11] Others further suppose a universal mind (see also panpsychism and panexperientialism). Other researchers have expressed similar objections to the introduction of any subjective element in the collapse of the wavefunction.[12][13][14]

Testability

It has been argued that the results of delayed-choice quantum eraser experiments empirically falsify this interpretation.[15] However, the argument was shown to be invalid because an interference pattern would only be visible after post-measurement detections were correlated through use of a coincidence counter;[16] if that was not true, the experiment would allow signaling into the past.[17] The delayed-choice quantum eraser experiment has also been used to argue for support of this interpretation,[18][19] but, as with other arguments, none of the cited references prove or falsify this interpretation.

The central role played by consciousness in this interpretation naturally calls for use of psychological experiments to verify or falsify it. One such approach relies on explaining the empirical presentiment effect quantum mechanically.[20] Another approach makes use of the psychological priming effect to design an appropriate test.[21] Both methods claim verification success.

Reception

A poll was conducted at a quantum mechanics conference in 2011 using 33 participants (including physicists, mathematicians, and philosophers). Researchers found that 6% of participants (2 of the 33) indicated that they believed the observer "plays a distinguished physical role (e.g., wave-function collapse by consciousness)". This poll also states that 55% (18 of the 33) indicated that they believed the observer "plays a fundamental role in the application of the formalism but plays no distinguished physical role". They also mention that "Popular accounts have sometimes suggested that the Copenhagen interpretation attributes such a role to consciousness. In our view, this is to misunderstand the Copenhagen interpretation."[22]

See also

References

  1. ^ a b c d e Chalmers, David J.; McQueen, Kelvin J. (2022-07-18), Gao, Shan (ed.), "Consciousness and the Collapse of the Wave Function", Consciousness and Quantum Mechanics, Oxford University Press, p. 0, ISBN 978-0-19-750166-5, retrieved 2025-04-11
  2. ^ a b c d e French, Steven (2020), Wiltsche, Harald A.; Berghofer, Philipp (eds.), "From a Lost History to a New Future: Is a Phenomenological Approach to Quantum Physics Viable?", Phenomenological Approaches to Physics, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 205–225, doi:10.1007/978-3-030-46973-3_10, ISBN 978-3-030-46973-3, retrieved 2025-04-11
  3. ^ F. London and E. Bauer, "La théorie de l'observation en mécanique quantique" (1939), English translation in Quantum Theory and Measurement, edited by J. A. Wheeler and W. H. Zurek, Princeton University, Princeton New Jersey, 1983, pp. 217–259. ISBN 0-691-08315-0
  4. ^ Wigner, Eugene; Henry Margenau (1967). "Remarks on the Mind Body Question, in Symmetries and Reflections, Scientific Essays". American Journal of Physics. 35 (12): 1169–1170. Bibcode:1967AmJPh..35.1169W. doi:10.1119/1.1973829. Archived from the original on 2013-01-12. Retrieved 2009-07-30.
  5. ^ a b c d e Schreiber, Zvi (1995-01-16). "The Nine Lives of Schroedinger's Cat". arXiv:quant-ph/9501014.
  6. ^ a b Michael Esfeld, (1999), Essay Review: Wigner's View of Physical Reality, published in Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 30B, pp. 145–154, Elsevier Science Ltd.
  7. ^ Heisenberg, W. (1958). Physics and Philosophy: The Revolution in Modern Science. Harper & Row.
  8. ^ Zurek, W. H. (2003). Decoherence, einselection, and the existential interpretation. Philosophy of Science, 70(5), 720-731.
  9. ^ H. Stapp (2001). "Quantum Theory and the Role of Mind in Nature". Foundations of Physics. 31 (10): 1465–1499. arXiv:quant-ph/0103043. doi:10.1023/A:1012682413597. S2CID 189823051.
  10. ^ Chalmers, David (1996). The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. Philosophy of Mind Series. Oxford University Press, USA. pp. 156–157. ISBN 978-0-19-983935-3.
  11. ^ Roger Penrose, The Emperor's New Mind, Penguin Books, 1989, p. 295.
  12. ^ Mandel, L. (1999). "Quantum effects in one-photon and two-photon interference". Reviews of Modern Physics. 71 (2): S274 – S282. Bibcode:1999RvMPS..71..274M. doi:10.1103/revmodphys.71.s274.
  13. ^ Zeilinger, A. (1999). "Experiment and the foundations of quantum physics". Reviews of Modern Physics. 71 (2): S288 – S297. Bibcode:1999RvMPS..71..288Z. doi:10.1103/revmodphys.71.s288.
  14. ^ Brukner, C.; Zeilinger, A. (2002). "Young's experiment and the finiteness of information". Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. 360 (1794): 1061–1069. arXiv:quant-ph/0201026. Bibcode:2002RSPTA.360.1061B. doi:10.1098/rsta.2001.0981. PMID 12804293. S2CID 16379957.
  15. ^ Yu, S.; Nikolić, D. (2011). "Quantum mechanics needs no consciousness" (PDF). Annalen der Physik. 523 (11): 931–938. Bibcode:2011AnP...523..931Y. doi:10.1002/andp.201100078. S2CID 122412883.
  16. ^ De Barros, J. Acacio; Oas, Gary (2017). "Can we falsify the consciousness-causes-collapse hypothesis in quantum mechanics?". Foundations of Physics. 47 (10): 1294–1308. arXiv:1609.00614. Bibcode:2017FoPh...47.1294D. doi:10.1007/s10701-017-0110-7. S2CID 118666353.
  17. ^ Andrew, Knight (2020). "Quantum mechanics may need consciousness". arXiv:2005.13317 [quant-ph].
  18. ^ Jacques, V.; Wu, E.; Grosshans, F.; Treussart, F.; Grangier, P.; Aspect, A.; Roch, J.-F. (2007). "Experimental Realization of Wheeler's Delayed-Choice Gedanken Experiment". Science. 315 (5814): 966–968. arXiv:quant-ph/0610241. Bibcode:2007Sci...315..966J. doi:10.1126/science.1136303. PMID 17303748. S2CID 6086068.
  19. ^ Ma, Xiao-Song; Zotter, Stefan; Kofler, Johannes; Ursin, Rupert; Jennewein, Thomas; Brukner, Časlav; Zeilinger, Anton (2012). "Experimental delayed-choice entanglement swapping". Nature Physics. 8 (6): 479–484. arXiv:1203.4834. Bibcode:2012NatPh...8..480M. doi:10.1038/nphys2294. S2CID 119208488.
  20. ^ Levin, E. Y. (2023-04-03). "The presentiment effect points to an occurrence of a von Neumann's collapse". Journal of Anomalous Experience and Cognition. 3 (1): 174–193. doi:10.31156/jaex.24455.
  21. ^ Lucido, R. J (2023). "Testing the consciousness causing collapse interpretation of quantum mechanics using subliminal primes derived from random fluctuations in radioactive decay". Journal of Consciousness Exploration & Research. 14 (3): 185–194. doi:10.13140/RG.2.2.20344.72969.
  22. ^ Schlosshauer, M.; Koer, J.; Zeilinger, A. (2013). "A Snapshot of Foundational Attitudes Toward Quantum Mechanics". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 44 (3): 222–230. arXiv:1301.1069. Bibcode:2013SHPMP..44..222S. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2013.04.004. S2CID 55537196.